In this section, we define analytic stacks and give some examples.
Reference.
This section is based on [8], Lecture 19. Remark 21.3.1 is taken from [8], Lecture 24.
Subsection21.1Definition of analytic stacks
Definition21.1.1.
An analytic stack is an accessible (Remark 19.2.1) functor \(F\colon \AnRing \to \Set\) with the following property: for any hypercovering \(\AnSpec(A_\bullet) \to \AnSpec(A)\) by \(!\)-able maps for which \(\calD(\Mod_A) \cong \lim^! \calD(\Mod_{A_\bullet})\text{,}\) we have
Let \(\AnStack\) be the category of analytic stacks.
For example, any representable functor is an analytic stack (and by Yoneda this defines a full embedding \(\AnRing^{\op} \to \AnStack\)). With this, the accessibility condition ensures that any object is a small colimit of representable functors.
Remark21.1.2.
This is not quite the definition of [8] because we are taking functors valued in sets, not something more simplicial. This difference is certainly relevant but will not appear in the examples we consider.
Example21.1.3.
Adic spaces, solid adic spaces, and dagger spaces all give rise to analytic stacks; in particular, the last of these include complex analytic spaces and Berkovich spaces. However, it is not clear that these functors are fully faithful.
Example21.1.4.
There is a functor \(\Sch \to \AnStack\) taking \(\Spec A\) to \(\AnSpec \underline{A}\) where the discrete condensed ring \(\underline{A}\) is interpreted as a discrete analytic ring. This functor is fully faithful by a theorem of Bhatt.
This construction extends further to algebraic stacks. For example, using Stone duality (Definition 19.3.3) we get a fully faithful functor \(\CSet \to \AnStack\text{.}\) This allows to give meaning to the assertion that the definition of a norm function on an analytic ring (Definition 18.2.2) corresponds to a morphism \(\AnSpec A \to [0,\infty]\) of analytic stacks; in this formulation, one can extend the definition immediately to arbitrary analytic stacks.
In addition, if we start with an analytic ring \(A\text{,}\) we can consider schemes over \(\Spec A^{\triangleright}\) and form the functor taking \(\Spec B\) to \(\AnSpec \underline{B}\) where \(\underline{B}\) is given the analytic ring structure induced from \(A\text{.}\) This again defines a functor to analytic stacks.
Subsection21.2Flavors of the Riemann sphere
To illustrate the richness of the category of analytic stacks, we indicate how some different flavors of the Riemann sphere interact within this category.
Example21.2.1.
We can form a sequence of morphisms of analytic stacks
\(X_1\) is the topological manifold \(S^2\text{.}\) This corresponds to taking the ring \(\Cts(S^2, \CC)\) over \(\CC_{\liquid}\text{.}\)
\(X_2\) is the \(C^\infty\) manifold \(S^2\text{.}\) This again corresponds to take the ring of global sections.
\(X_3\) is the real analytic manifold \(S^2\text{.}\) This cannot be treated globally; instead it is created by glueing as in Section 17.
\(X_4\) is the complex analytic manifold \(S^2\text{.}\) This is again created by glueing.
\(X_5\) is the scheme \(\PP^1_\CC\text{.}\) This is again created by glueing.
\(X_6\) is the topological space \(S^2\) treated as a condensed set. As a reminder, this is created by covering \(S^2\) with a profinite set.
Theorem 17.5.3 implies that \(X_4 \to X_5\) is an isomorphism of analytic stacks! The other maps are not isomorphisms.
Subsection21.3A final remark
Remark21.3.1.
One potential use of this setup is to construct the sort of virtual fundamental classes which are needed all over the place in enumerative geometry. These are needed to count intersections of two geometric objects in cases where the “expected dimension” of the intersection is 0 but things can sometimes behave more badly. This is fairly familiar in algebraic geometry, where various techniques exist to handle this (moving lemmas, deformation to the normal cone) but is much more problematic in less rigid geometries, such as symplectic geometry (where such enumerative questions are fundamental in mirror symmetry).
A model case of this can be seen by considering \(R = \Cts(\RR, \RR)\) as a condensed ring. It can be shown that for \(f \in R\text{,}\) the isomorphism class of the quotient \(R/(f)\) determines \(f\) up to a unit; in particular this can be used to detect whether \(f\) has a sign crossing at one of its zeroes, even when the Taylor series of \(f\) is identically zero.
Subsection21.4Material to be removed
Lemma21.4.1.
Let \(A\) be a solid analytic ring. Then for any \(f \in A(*)\text{,}\) for \(g \in \{1, 1-f\}\text{,}\) for any \(M \in \Mod_A\text{,}\) the sequence
\begin{equation*}
0\to M \to M \otimes_A A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \tfrac{f}{g} \right\rangle \oplus
M \otimes_A A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \tfrac{g}{f} \right\rangle \to
M \otimes_A A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \tfrac{f}{g}, \tfrac{g}{f} \right\rangle \to 0
\end{equation*}
is exact.
Proof.
Since the map in Lemma 13.2.1 (taking \(R := A^{\triangleright}\)) is an isomorphism, it remains an isomorphism after tensoring with \(A\text{.}\) Meanwhile, by Corollary 13.1.5, the sequences used in the proof of Lemma 13.2.2 remain exact after tensoring with \(M\text{,}\) so we may emulate the argument therein.
Definition21.4.2.
Let \(A \to B\) be a rational localization of solid analytic rings corresponding to parameters \(f_1,\dots,f_n,g\in A^{\triangleright}(*)\) which generate the unit ideal. We can then factor this map through \(A \to B_0\) where
we call the map \(A \to B_0\) the loose rational localization defined by \(f_1,\dots,f_n,g\text{.}\)
Define the loose adic topology on \(\AnRing^{\op}\) as the Grothendieck topology generated by coverings by families of loose rational localizations \(A \to A_{i,0}\) arising from sequences \(f_1,\dots,f_n \in A^{\triangleright}(*)\) generating the unit ideal.
For \(A\) a solid analytic ring, for \(f,g \in A^{\triangleright}(*)\) which generate the unit ideal, for any \(A \in \Mod_A\text{,}\) the sequence
\begin{equation*}
0 \to M \to M \otimes_A A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \frac{f}{g} \right\rangle
\oplus M \otimes_A A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \frac{g}{f} \right\rangle \to
M \otimes_A A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \frac{f}{g}, \frac{g}{f} \right\rangle \to 0
\end{equation*}
is exact.
Proof.
In the case where \(g=1\) or \(g=1-f\) this was already established in Lemma 21.4.1. By this plus Proposition 12.3.8, we may check the general case locally with respect to a refinement of the binary covering defined by \(f,g\text{.}\) In particular, we may assume without loss of generality that \(A = A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \frac{f}{g} \right\rangle\text{,}\) in which case also \(A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \frac{g}{f} \right\rangle = A^{\triangleright} \left\langle \frac{f}{g}, \frac{g}{f} \right\rangle\) and so the sequence in question is split exact.
Lemma21.4.4.
For \(A\) a solid analytic ring, for \(f,g \in A^{\triangleright}(*)\) which generate the unit ideal, the map
The truth of Theorem 21.4.5 may seem surprising in light of the fact that tensoring with even a loose rational localizations is not an exact morphism (Example 9.1.6). The point is that loose rational localizations are at least universally injective (Corollary 13.1.5) and this is sufficient for descent of modules (compare [28], tag 08WE for the case of modules over discrete rings). However, the failure of base extension along a loose rational localization to be flat is a compelling argument to introduce derived categories at this point.
Lemma21.4.7.
For \(A\) a sheafy solid analytic ring, for \(f,g \in A^{\triangleright}(*)\) which generate the unit ideal, the map
By Lemma 21.4.4, the functor is fully faithful. To check essential surjectivity, we may apply Remark 14.1.2 to an element of the target category to obtain a complex concentrated in degrees 0 and 1. However, we can then apply Lemma 21.4.4 again to see that the cohomology in degree 1 vanishes.
Remark21.4.8.
The issues raised in Remark 21.4.6 and Remark 14.1.3 become more acute when we switch from the loose adic topology back to the adic topology, where Lemma 21.4.7 no longer applies: the base extension along a rational localization includes an analytic completion step which is not exact. So the best we can hope to assert is that some sort of derived category of \(\Mod_A\) is a stack for the adic topology, but this is obstructed in the same manner as in Remark 14.1.3.
As a first step, we can at least formulate the analogue of Remark 14.1.2. A complete resolution will have to wait until we introduce the \(\infty\)-categorical analogue of the derived category of \(\Mod_A\text{.}\)
Lemma21.4.9.
Let \(A\) be a solid analytic ring and choose \(f,g \in A^{\triangleright}(*)\) generating the unit ideal. Then the base extension functor
To see that \(\underline{\ZZ[q]} \to P\) is flat, we may argue as in Lemma 13.1.3: form the exact sequence
\begin{equation*}
0 \to \underline{\ZZ[q]} \otimes P \stackrel{\times (q-[1])}{\to} \underline{\ZZ[q]} \otimes P \to P \to 0\text{,}
\end{equation*}
then observe that for any \(M \in \Mod_{\underline{\ZZ[q]}}\text{,}\)\(M \otimes_{\underline{\ZZ[q]}} \underline{\ZZ[q]} \otimes P \cong M \otimes P\) injects into \(M \otimes (P \oplus \prod_{n \lt 0} \ZZ[n])\) on which multiplication by \(q-[1] = [1](1 - q[-1])\) is an isomorphism.