Skip to main content

Section 15 Proof of the Hodge-Tate comparison

Reference.

[18], lecture VI; [25], sections 5, 6.
In this section, we prove the Hodge-Tate comparison theorem (Theorem 12.4.1). Our strategy will be to build up from the special case treated in Section 14, in which we used the crystalline prism (Zp,(p)) as the base and the ring R=Fp[x1,,xr].
We also assert the crystalline and de Rham comparison theorems. These are technically a bit more involved, so we do not include all of the details here.
Throughout, we fix a bounded prism (A,I) and denote its slice A/I by A.

Subsection 15.1 Étale localization and base change

Remark 15.1.1.

Recall that a morphism RS of rings is smooth if and only if locally on Spec(S), it can be written in the form RR[x1,,xr]S where the second map is étale (see [117], tag 054L). Similarly, if RS is a p-completely smooth map, then locally on Spec(S/p) it can be written in the form RRx1,,xrS where the second map is p-completely étale (use Proposition 6.5.3 to reduce to the previous statement).
If AR is p-completely smooth, then Ω^R/A1 is a finite projective R-module (again by Proposition 6.5.3 to reduce to the corresponding statement about differentials for a smooth morphism). Consequently, if RS is p-completely étale, then Ω^R/Ai^RSΩ^S/Ai for all i.
This suggests the strategy of proving the Hodge-Tate comparison for a general p-completely smooth A-algebra R by proving the corresponding compatibility with étale maps, and then using this to reduce to the case R=AX1,,Xr. The first step in this program is executed by Lemma 15.1.2.

Proof.

The restriction functor (S/A)Δ(R/A)Δ admits a right adjoint F taking (BB/IBR) to (BSBS/IBSS) where BS/IBS=B/IB^RLS and BBS is the unique lift of the étale morphism B/IBB/IB^RLS given by the the henselian property of derived completions (see Corollary 6.3.2), promoted from Ring to Ringδ using Exercise 6.7.11. Applying F to a weakly final object of (R/A)Δ (Proposition 11.6.5), we obtain a weakly final object of (S/A)Δ; since F also preserves finite products, we can take a complex computing ΔR/A and apply F term by term to obtain a complex computing ΔS/A. It thus remains to compare this with ΔR/A^RLS; we have a natural isomorphism at the level of simplicial rings, and (since RS is I-completely flat and thus has finite I-complete Tor amplitude) we may now deduce the claim from Exercise 10.6.3. (Compare [25], Lemma 4.19.)
Another tool we will use is a base-change assertion. This will allow us to simplify the base ring A in some cases.

Proof.

Let (P,IP) be a weakly final object of (R/A)Δ, then apply Remark 11.6.7 to construct a Čech-Alexander complex computing ΔR/A. Then ΔR/A is computed by the complex obtained by applying ^AA termwise. Under the hypothesis on the Tor amplitude, we may apply Exercise 10.6.3 to conclude. (Compare [25], Lemma 4.18.)
As an immediate application of étale localization and base change, we upgrade our previous statement about the Hodge-Tate comparison for crystalline prisms (Proposition 14.4.12).

Proof.

Subsection 15.2 Comparing a universal prism to a crystalline prism

Remark 15.2.1.

We reproduce [18], Lecture VI, Remark 2.2, in order to justify why we can’t directly transpose the proof of the Hodge-Tate comparison from crystalline prisms to more general prisms. Suppose that I=(d). Consider the object P=A[x]Ringδ with δ(x)=0. Then the derived (p,d)-completion of P{ϕ(x)/d} does not equal the derived (p,d)-completion of the divided power envelope of (P,(x)). A typical example of this is the case (A,(d))=(Zp[[q1]],([p]q)); in this case, the derived (p,d)-completion of P{ϕ(x)/d} will end up coinciding with the derived (p,d)-completion of the q-divided power envelope of (P,(x)).

Proof.

Since A is p-torsion-free, B is not just derived p-complete but also classically p-complete. Since dp=p(ϕ(d)/pδ(p)) is divisible by p, B is also classically (p,d)-complete. By Corollary 14.3.4, B equals the classical p-completion of the divided power envelope of (A,(d)). (Compare [25], Construction 6.1.)

Remark 15.2.3.

In the notation of Lemma 15.2.2, B is again a δ-ring and both ϕ(d) and p are distinguished elements. Since ϕ(d) is divisible by p, we may apply Lemma 5.2.1 to deduce that ϕ(d) and p generate the same ideal in B. In other words, the composition of maps of δ-rings
ABϕBB
promotes to a composition of maps of prisms
(A,(d))(B,(d))ϕB(B,(ϕ(d)))=(B,(p))
in which the target is crystalline! This will ultimately allow us to transfer information from the crystalline case of the Hodge-Tate comparison to the universal case, and then from there to the general case.

Proof.

In (1), the first map has finite (p,d)-complete Tor amplitude because d is not a zero-divisor in A/p; the second and third maps are faithfully flat by construction. (Compare [25], Construction 6.1.)

Proof.

Subsection 15.3 Hodge-Tate comparisons

We finally treat the Hodge-Tate comparison theorem (Theorem 12.4.1) in general. Before treating the general case, we give an easier argument that covers many cases of interest.

Proof.

By Lemma 15.1.2, we may reduce to the case R=Ax1,,xr. In this case, since we assumed the map (A0,(d))(A,(d)) from the universal oriented prism has finite (p,d)-complete Tor amplitude, we can use Lemma 15.1.3 to transfer the desired result from (A0,(d)) (to which Proposition 15.2.5 applies) to (A,(d)). (Compare [25], Proposition 6.2.)

Proof.

Again by Lemma 15.1.2, we may reduce to the case R=Ax1,,xr. Using Lemma 5.2.5, we can further reduce to the case where (A,I)=(A,(d)) is an oriented prism. Let (A0,(d))(A,(d)) be the morphism from the universal oriented prism. Form a diagram as in Proposition 15.2.5 in which α is the map from Lemma 15.2.2 and the square is a pushout of (p,d)-complete simplicial commutative rings. (The key technical complication here is that E is not necessarily an ordinary ring.)
Figure 15.3.3.
The arrow ZpD0 promotes to a map (Zp,(p))(D0,(p)) of prisms, so we also have a map γ:(Zp,(p))(E,(p)) of oriented prisms. Using the explicit description of prismatic cohomology given in Corollary 14.4.4, we may produce a natural isomorphism β^ΔR/Aγ^ΔFp[x1,,xr]/Zp. By Proposition 14.4.12, we know that the Hodge-Tate comparison map is an isomorphism for the prism (Zp,(p)) and the ring Fp[x1,,xr]; combining this with the previous isomorphism, we deduce that the original Hodge-Tate comparison map becomes an isomorphism after applying β^. Since this last functor is conservative (because α^ is conservative by Lemma 15.2.4), it is itself an isomorphism. (Compare [25], Proposition 6.2.)

Subsection 15.4 The crystalline and de Rham comparisons

On a related note, we describe the comparison between prismatic, crystalline, and de Rham cohomology under some mild restrictions (in addition to our running condition that (A,I) is bounded). One complication is that we do not have an analogue of Lemma 15.1.2 for prismatic cohomology: for RS an I-completely etale morphism of A-algebras, there is no obvious base change functor to relate ΔR/A to ΔS/A.

Proof.

The key point is to construct the map, as thereafter one can compute in local coordinates as in the proof of Lemma 14.4.8. See [25], Theorem 5.2.

Remark 15.4.2.

Before continuing, we make an observation that will explain a somewhat odd condition in Theorem 15.4.3. Recall that by construction, the p-typical Witt vector functor W is a right adjoint to the forgetful functor RingδRing (Definition 3.1.1). We may thus apply adjunction to the canonical map AA to obtain a morphism AW(A) in Ringδ.
Now let ψ:AW(A) be the composition of the resulting map with the Frobenius ϕ on W(A). This map carries I into (p): the original map AW(A) carries I into the image of the Verschiebung V on W(A), and the composition ϕV is multiplication by p (Definition 3.2.3). Hence the map ψ induces a morphism (A,I)(W(A),(p)) of prisms provided that W(A) is p-torsion-free (so that the target is actually a prism).

Proof.

In light of Remark 15.4.2, it is enough to construct a functorial isomorphism of ΔR/A^A,ψLW(A)ΔR/W(A), where R=R^A,ψW(A)/p (and the stated isomorphism is given by Lemma 15.1.3), with the crystalline cohomology of R/p with coefficients in W(A). This amounts to an application of Theorem 15.4.1. (Compare [25], Theorem 6.4.)

Remark 15.4.4.

In Theorem 15.4.3, the condition that W(A) is p-torsion-free holds in two natural cases of interest: when A/I is p-torsion-free, or when I=(p) and A is reduced. The result remains true without this condition, but this is more difficult and falls outside the scope of these notes; see [25], Corollary 15.4.